An important reason that well-founded relations are interesting is because a version of transfinite induction can be used on them: if is a well-founded relation, P is some property of elements of X, and we want to show that it suffices to show that: That is, Well-founded induction is sometimes called Noetherian induction, after Emmy Noether. On par with induction, well-founded relations also support construction of objects by transfinite recursion. Let be a set-like well-founded relation and F a function that assigns an object F to each pair of an element x ∈ X and a function g on the initial segment of X. Then there is a unique function G such that for every x ∈ X, That is, if we want to construct a function G on X, we may define G using the values of G for y R x. As an example, consider the well-founded relation, where N is the set of all natural numbers, and S is the graph of the successor functionx ↦ x+1. Then induction on S is the usual mathematical induction, and recursion on S gives primitive recursion. If we consider the order relation, we obtain complete induction, and course-of-values recursion. The statement that is well-founded is also known as the well-ordering principle. There are other interesting special cases of well-founded induction. When the well-founded relation is the usual ordering on the class of all ordinal numbers, the technique is called transfinite induction. When the well-founded set is a set of recursively-defined data structures, the technique is called structural induction. When the well-founded relation is set membership on the universal class, the technique is known as ∈-induction. See those articles for more details.
Examples
Well-founded relations which are not totally ordered include:
the set of all finite strings over a fixed alphabet, with the order defined by s < t if and only if s is a proper substring of t.
the set N × N of pairs of natural numbers, ordered by < if and only if n1 < m1 and n2 < m2.
the set of all regular expressions over a fixed alphabet, with the order defined by s < t if and only if s is a proper subexpression of t.
any class whose elements are sets, with the relation . This is the axiom of regularity.
the nodes of any finite directed acyclic graph, with the relation R defined such that a R b if and only if there is an edge from a to b.
Examples of relations that are not well-founded include:
the negative integers, with the usual order, since any unbounded subset has no least element.
The set of strings over a finite alphabet with more than one element, under the usual order, since the sequence "B" > "AB" > "AAB" > "AAAB" > … is an infinite descending chain. This relation fails to be well-founded even though the entire set has a minimum element, namely the empty string.
the rational numbers under the standard ordering, since, for example, the set of positive rationals lacks a minimum.
Other properties
If is a well-founded relation and x is an element ofX, then the descending chains starting at x are all finite, but this does not mean that their lengths are necessarily bounded. Consider the following example: Let X be the union of the positive integers and a new element ω, which is bigger than any integer. Then X is a well-founded set, but there are descending chains starting at ω of arbitrary great length; the chain ω, n − 1, n − 2,..., 2, 1 has length n for any n. The Mostowski collapse lemma implies that set membership is a universal among the extensional well-founded relations: for any set-like well-founded relation R on a class X which is extensional, there exists a class C such that is isomorphic to.
Reflexivity
A relation R is said to be reflexive if aRa holds for every a in the domain of the relation. Every reflexive relation on a nonempty domain has infinite descending chains, because any constant sequence is a descending chain. For example, in the natural numbers with their usual order ≤, we have To avoid these trivial descending sequences, when working with a partial order ≤, it is common to apply the definition of well foundedness to the alternate relation < defined such that a < b if and only if a ≤ b and a ≠ b. More generally, when working with a preorder ≤, it is common to use the relation < defined such that a < b if and only if a ≤ b and b ≰ a. In the context of the natural numbers, this means that the relation <, which is well-founded, is used instead of the relation ≤, which is not. In some texts, the definition of a well-founded relation is changed from the definition above to include these conventions.